2018-04-16 RRG Notes
- Our brains automatically categorize things by similarity, regardless of the formal logical rules we set out
- This is a good thing
- The brain does not treat words as purely logical construsts
- Given that, it is a mistake to rely on any system of thinking that relies on you being able to treat words as purely logical constructs
- The mere act of creating a word causes your mind to create a category and thus trigger unconscious inferences
- An intensional definition is a definition given in terms of other words, as a dictionary does
- An extensional definition is a definition given by showing a cluster of objects that share the given property
- Both are ways of communicating concepts to others
- Both have their limitations
- A complete intensional definition that fully captures a concept is extremely verbose and unwieldy, even for simple concepts
- A complete extensional definition for a concept might require enumerating an infinite set
- The strongest definitions use a combination of intensional and extensional communication to draw a boundary that captures a concept
- However, even a perfect definition is only instructions for building a concept, not a concept in and of itself
- You can't control a concept's intension, because most intensions are applied subconsciously
- As a result, you can't make a word mean anything you want - you don't have full control over the meanings your brain assigns to words
- The notion of a configuration space is a way of translating object descriptions to positions in a multidimensional space
- We can think of individual objects as being positions in a vast multi-dimensional thingspace
- We can visualize categories as clouds within this thingspace, encompassing many individual objects
- This gives us a way of thinking about what constitutes a "typical" element of a category - it is the object that is closest to the center of the cloud
- Visualizing categories in this manner allows us to retain flexibility regarding atypical members of a category
- Instead of arguing whether ostriches and penguins are or are not birds, we can say they're atypical birds, whereas a robin is a more typical bird
- Most intensional definitions will have a few exceptions, but they can still be useful if they can broadly demarcate a "cloud of things"
- Intensional definitions need only to serve as pointers to similarity clusters
- Once we have the similarity cluster in our head, we can think about the cluster directly, without necessarily worrying about whether a particular element of the cluster satisfies every aspect of the intensional definition, or whether the intensional definition captures things outside of the cluster
- Our notions of typicality bias our thinking
- People say that it is more likely that a disease will spread from robins to ducks than from ducks to robins, presumably because robins are the more "typical" bird
- People say that 98 is closer to 100 than 100 is to 98
- People take typicality as an inherent property of an object, rather than a property derived from the set that the object belongs to
- Kansas is "close" and Alaska is "far away" regardless of where you are, because Kansas is a central state whereas Alaska is a peripheral state
- This is another reason to stop pretending that words can be treated as purely abstract classes